Is Modernity Colonial? How so?
“Now it so happens that during the struggle for
liberation, at the moment that the native intellectual comes into touch again
with his people, this artificial sentinel is turned into dust.” – Frantz Fanon (2001: 36)
In
his seminal work, The Wretched of the
Earth, Frantz Fanon describes the native intellectual’s gradual
disillusionment with the values of Western society. For Fanon, the values of
modernity, liberal rational progress toward an enlightened humanity, represent
in actual practice the moral justification for the divide between the
colonizing Self and the native Other. As the native intellectual becomes aware
of the true struggle located in the people of the countryside, the values of
Western modernity come to be realized as a tool of oppression rather than
liberation. For Fanon, it is in the struggle of the people that true
enlightenment is to take place. Though Fanon’s vision of a third world
liberated from the values of Western civilization has not been realized in
contemporary society, his diagnosis of modernity as essential to the colonial
project rings true. The very idea of progress essential to modernity and the
idea of the modern as new relies on the construction of a backward Other in
order to sustain itself. This discursive power of modernity and the global
shift in material power that takes place during the 19th century
mutually reinforce each other in the creation and subsistence of global
hierarchies of Self and Other. The
colonial nature of these relations lay the discursive foundation for what
Partha Chatterjee terms a ‘global practice of power’ based on the metropole’s
potential power to declare the colonial exception. In locating the colonial
tendency in a unique shift in the philosophy and history of modernity I also
aim to expose the limits of liberal humanistic philosophies’ ability to examine
the nature of the colonial situation that they are complicit in creating.
This
paper proceeds in three distinct parts. First, an examination of Tzvetan
Todorov’s work The Conquest of America:
The Question of the Other takes place in order to lay a philosophical
foundation for a critique of the modern project as the bifurcation of Self and
Other. While Todorov lays out an impressive framework to establish the
problematique of Self/Other relations his own faith in the modern project leads
him to the reproduction of the same categories that he sought to avoid. Todorov’s
philosophical definition of modernity and his subject of study also lead him to
underestimate the social, political and economic effects of historical
modernity that take place during the nineteenth century. The second part of
this paper uses Partha Chatterjee’s The
Black Hole of Empire: A Global Practice of Power as a critique of the
shortcomings of Todorov. It is also in Chatterjee that we find the
norm-deviation structure that lays out the discursive framework for a colonial
modernity as well as a distinct shift in global power relations. Both the
discursive power and the material power reinforce each other and culminate in
the power to declare the colonial exception and the ultimate representation of
the colonial relations of modernity. Finally this paper will examine Todorov
from the point of view of the oppressed using Frantz Fanon’sThe Wretched of the Earth to examine the
implications for a gaze from liberal modernity that looks critically at itself
but from a position of unacknowledged power.
Before
moving to Todorov, it is important to define what I mean by modernity. As
Frederick Cooper (2005: 113) has recently pointed out the deployment of the
word ‘modernity’ has so many different meanings that the usefulness of the term
itself comes into question. In this essay, two interrelated definitions of
modernity emerge; a philosophical definition of modernity and a historical
definition of modernity. The philosophical definition of modernity defines what
it means to be a modern. It is the discourse used to distinguish the modern
epoch from theprevious.Simplifying to an extent, philosophical modernity is
defined by a belief that through reason man (as individuals) can progress to a
fundamentally better life than the one before. (Pippin, 2003: 4) While defining
itself in juxtaposition to life before, philosophical modernity relies on the
construction of the irrational, traditional Other to justify the progressive,
reasonable Self.
The historical definition of
modernity refers to the long nineteenth century (Hobsbawm 1996) and the social,
political and economic global transformation that takes place during that time.
As Barry Buzan and George Lawson (2013: 621) argue the global transformation
revolve around three key changes: the rise of industrial capitalism, the
emergence of the nation-state and, closely linked with philosophical modernity,
ideologies of progress. The global transformation grounds these discourses of
modernity in historical context that demonstrate how the process of
colonization itself created and reinforced social, political and economic
global hierarchies. It is important to note that both the ideology of
philosophical modernity and the social consequences of the nineteenth century
played out in a messy and uneven process that was particular to different
historical contexts. Nonetheless, seeing philosophical modernity and historical
modernity in tandem exposes how the social, political and economic consequences
of the nineteenth century and the narratives established by the philosophers of
modernity reinforce one another. Through this mutual co-constitution, not only
of historical and philosophical modernity, but of East and West, the ‘global
practice of power’ emerges around the power to declare the colonial exception.
Tzvetan Todorov’s The Conquest of America: The Question of the
Other demonstrates a lucid attempt to come to terms with the philosophical
implications of modernity for Self/Other relations. Todorov’s work ultimately
fails, however, because he stays committed to the very modern project he seems
to indict in his book. For Todorov the genocidal encounter between the
Spanish Conquistadors and the Native Americans constitutes the formative moment
in the understanding of Western modernity. In his retelling Todorov aims to
tell a moral history of the present in order to answer the question: “How to do
deal with the other?” Central to this project is Todorov’s commitment to a
narrative style throughout his work and more often than not attempts to allow
the words of the actors involved in this interaction speak for themselves.
While remaining committed to an open narrative style throughout the text,
towards the end of the work Todorov proposes that through this victory of
semiotics, European logos has conquered mythos. Todorov
simultaneously implicates modernity in the utter destruction of an entire
peoples, which acknowledging the potential for modernity to rectify modernity’s
breaking with the world and bring it back into harmony. I argue that Todorov’s
argument is a profound step in the indictment of modernity as destructive, but
that in attempting to recover some of the healthy parts of philosophical
modernity it does not recognize the reliance the
modern Self has on the construction of the Other. Modernity is not the
discovery of the colonial Other, it is the very creation of it.
At
the heart of Todorov’s argument in The
Conquest of America is the idea that the genocidal encounter between the
Spanish Conquistadors and the Native Americans was a defining moment in the
identity formation of modernity. Todorov’s explanation for choosing this
historical event as the subject for his moral investigation is predicated on
this encounter as specifically unique because it was a genuine encounter
between two previously unknown peoples. (Todorov, 1999: 4) This radical
encounter with the Other, for Todorov symbolizes a defining moment in modernity
because it “establishes our present identity.” (Todorov, 1999: 5) Through this
event, Todorov argues, “men have discovered the totality of which they are a
part.” (Todorov, 1999:5) The implications for this argument that is that the
encounter between radical others and the means of victory of one civilization, logos,
over another, mythos, shapes our present understanding of the world
today. (Todorov, 1999:253) As part of
his moral project, he hopes to propose his work through a narrative style
instead of imposing it through systematic analysis. Similarly, Todorov is
sensitive to the critique of promoting European superiority and goes to lengths
to discount the possibility. The complexities of Todorov’s argument caution us
against thinking in terms of European superiority.
Todorov
argues that what is uniquely modern and exhibits the capacity for
destruction is the radical othering itself. The victory of logos
over mythos takes place because the Spanish utilizedlanguage to act
whereas the Aztecs reacted.
Todorov (1999: 89-90) argues that “for the Aztecs, signs automatically and
necessarily proceed from the world they designate, rather than being a weapon
intended to manipulate the Other.”Todorov (1999: 112) goes on to demonstrate
how the cold, calculating and rational manipulation of signs by Cortes
is part of a coherent strategy to bring about the end of the Other.It is the
use of signs as a weapon for manipulation that logos should be
associated with. Here Todorov (1999: 145) seems to be indicting the
philosophical modernity of reasoned, rational progress based on the individual
in the civilization of massacre. Instead of being seen as natural progress
toward an enlightened and ultimately better world, logos is complicit
with the manipulation of the Other. Not only is it complicit in the
manipulation of the Other, but it is also a part of the utter and horrific
destruction of the Other. He explains: “But this victory from which we all
derive…delivers as well a terrible blow to our capacity to feel harmony with
the world.” (Todorov, 1999: 97)However, Todorov’s faith in the liberal
humanistic project of philosophical modernity is evident in his belief that the
world has the capability of being brought into harmony. It is in this
juxtaposition between the capacity for the destruction latent in modernity and
Todorov’s conviction in project of bringing the world through understanding
that the cracks in Todorov’s argument begin to be exposed.
In
answering Todorov’s original question, “How to deal with the other?” it is the
Othering itself that seems to lead to aberrant destruction. Todorov (1999: 144)
argues that “The more remote and alien the victims, the better, they are
exterminated without remorse, more or less identified with animals.” Todorov
highlights two equally unappealing sides to the reasoning of the Spaniards. The
first, exemplified by an early Las Casas is one of equality corrupted into
identity and therefore necessary assimilation and colonization. The second,
highlighted by Gines de Selpuveda, is that of difference but also inequality,
inferiority and therefore enslavement or destruction.
Both
figures represent a failure on the part of philosophical modernity to
adequately deal with the question of the Other. In Las Casas we have a figure
(identifiable in contemporary society with human rights advocates) who seeks to
project his universal values onto the Other and assimilate him into the
‘correct’ way of life. Though Las Casas bases his universalism on Christianity
(Todorov, 1999: 160-161), Todorov’s critique can also be read as one of liberal
universalism that seeks to extend the same rights of man to the globe. In
Todorov’s (1999:153) reading of Sepulveda we have a critique of the idea that
in order for the modern Self to establish itself relies on the binaries
established around Self/Other that follow the logic of good/evil. At the same
time that Todorov critiques philosophical modernity, his solution and faith in
a rational reconfiguration of how to deal with the Other represents complicity
with the same project. The solution is a balance between the two whereby we
experience “difference in equality.” (Todorov, 1999: 250) Key to this argument
is the difference between proposing and imposing.
This
“difference in equality” is exemplified by combining the figure of Bernando de
Sahagun, who lays down the foundations for a potential future dialogue and the
solution to the problem of “the Other”, with that of Cabeza de Vaca. Sahagun’s
dialogue is comparable to that of Todorov, who mirrors his method in order to
discover the Other in his own work. For Sahagun, as for Todorov, a dialogue
between cultures cannot be reduced to a method, the words must be allowed to
speak for themselves and a hybridization of cultures must be resisted. The
intention for both authors is to “juxtapose voices.” (Todorov, 1999: 241) This
is the beginning of a potential dialogue across cultures for Todorov (1999:
153) for through this dialogue one can propose instead of impose.Similarly
Cabeza de Vaca represents a certain modernity in the symbol of the modern
exile, who is no longer purely one (as exemplified by the universalism of
Christianity), but is instead suspended between two different cultures,
belonging to neither. (Todorov, 1999: 250) This figure is also echoed by
that La Malinche, of whom Todorov (1999, 100) says represents “we are
inevitably bi- or tri-cultural.”While acknowledging the incredible destruction
caused at the outset of modernity, Todorov also recognizes the tremendous
potential of modernity to overcome the problem of the Other.
Far
from Todorov’s narrative style being a celebration of logos conquering mythos, it
is actually a response to it. The ethical principles to adhere to is that moral
reasoning is possible when information is democratized and used as nonviolent
communication. (Todorov, 1999: 182) Similarly, Todorov believes that by
bringing two narratives together in juxtaposition, he can propose rather than
impose his moral critique, which is contingent because it is not based on the
natural superiority of one over the other. But this in itself can be read as
complicit with the modern philosophical project. The potential for progress
comes in because history and culture is contingent and relative and by
recognizing this contingency we open ourselves up to “imperceptible shifts.”
(Todorov, 1999: 254) Language, reason and a faith in progress, despite its
tremendous capacity for destruction, also has the incredible capacity for
construction and so logos retains its value in its potential to bring
the world back into harmony. But in retaining his faith in logosand the modern philosophical project Todorov fails to grasp
the true nature of the relationship between modernity and colonialism and opens
himself up to critique.
Todorov
begins to expose the problematic of the modern condition based on the
juxtaposition between the Self/Otherbut fails to recognize how his own faith in
progress and logos is complicit in
the very creation of the Other.Todorov’s failure is evident in the way he
reproduces the myth of the ‘noble savage’ he seeks to discredit. In the
reproduction of the myth, Todorov (with the possible exception of the figure of
La Malinche) does not give sufficient agency to the Other and ignores the
struggle that takes place over identity between Self/Other. Similarly, by
choosing a study based on the conquest of America, Todorov is equally
inattentive to the social, political and economic consequences of the
co-constitution of philosophical and historical modernity and that limit the
potential for non-violent dialogue to take place. In order to critique and
rectify Todorov’s project, it is to Partha Chatterjee’s The Black Hole of Empire that we turn. Chatterjee
shows how the norm-deviation structure of modern European philosophy lay the
discursive framework of a global practice of power. In doing so, he exposes the
shortcomings of Todorov and explicates the social consequences of modernity as
well as the co-constitution of the modern subject through Self/Other relations.
The power to decide the colonial exception combined with modernity’s unique
capacity for destruction renders modernity explicitly colonial. The very
constitution of the modern world would be unimaginable without colonial
relations.
In Chatterjee one reads an
important distinction between the early modern and the modern with the former
providing a space of potential action and the modern as a place where these
practices are subsumed. The early modern in Chatterjee’s (2012: 125) Bengal
still relies on hierarchical relations of Self/Other that constitute colonial
relations. But the early modern as well represented a moment where “there was a
more public and political domain where the idea of the
citizen-subject-educated, enlightened, responsible, and conscious of his
freedoms.” (Chatterjee, 2012: 125) In recovering the figures of Tipu, Tagore
and Rammohan Chatterjee (2012:157) hopes to demonstrate the self-awareness that
Indians possessed on the modern questions of state organization, and the
freedom of the citizen. In the modern, the complex discursive structure of
social relations manifested itself so that “its impact on the next phase of the
historical development of colonial empire was reduced to insignificance.”
(Chatterjee, 2012: 157) That Chatterjee distinguishes this ‘modern’ era in
Indian from the early modern indicates an awareness of the full consequences of
both philosophical and historical modernity coming to fruition at this time and
it is to this formative era that one must now turn. (Chatterjee, 2012: 76)
The modern for Chatterjee is
distinguished by a norm deviation structure that lays the discursive foundation
for imperial relations and the manifestations of this in the historical
practice in pedagogies of violence and culture. In Chatterjee one sees a fuller
picture of modernity as a set of colonial relations emerging from the
co-constitution of a philosophical modernity of progressive ideology and the
historical modernity of uneven power relations. Chatterjee (2012: 167-173)
finds in the liberal utilitarian philosophies of J.S. Mill, Jeremy Bentham the
technique and moral foundations of empire. Their philosophies that fed the
discourse of norm-deviation is largely consistent with the definition of
philosophical modernity outlined above. In implicating these thinkers in the
very nature of colonial modernity, Chatterjee points to the ideal of the
liberal modern as an inherently colonial one. These philosophies (even in their
universalistic guises) are based on difference, exclusion and control instead
of equality and emancipation.
The principle of norm-deviation
that is essential to Chatterjee’s conception of modernity rests on gradations
of civilization. Jeremy Bentham began the technique of categorizing colonies on
a universal standard and then applying different policies to bring them up to
that standard. (Chatterjee, 2012: 168, 172)For Chatterjee (2012:186): “The norm
deviation structure would establish the empirical location of any particular
social formation at any given time in relation to the empirically prevailing
average or normal.” Once a deviation had been tracked it could then be
rectified by an appropriate policy so that it could progress to the universally
desirable norm. (Chatterjee 2012, 174) In the colonies, where the people where
the people were not yet civilized enough for self-rule, the best way to ensure
their progress to a desirable level of civilization was through paternal
despotism, a position advocated by JS Mill and supplemented by the philosophies
of John Locke. (Chatterjee, 2012: 177) For the colonies, an exception had to be
declared. It is evident how the paternal despotism of Mill and the idea of
progress towards a universal norm advocated by Bentham relies on the
progressive liberal philosophies of modernity. What is also evident is that
these philosophies rely on a policy of distinction between the binaries of Self
and Other, between civilized and uncivilized and between those who can
determine the norm and those who cannot.
Unlike Todorov’s position that
appears to indicate the emergence of Self-Other hierarchies should be located
in the mind of the individual, Chatterjee emphasizes that these discursive
formations would not be possible if they were not grounded in certain
historical practices. The philosophy of norm-deviation both emerged from and
fed into the history of modernity. Chatterjee locates three historical shifts
that both enable and inform the norm-deviation structure, legal positivism,
industrial capitalism, and a policy of balance of power among the European
great powers. Legal positivism marked a shift from natural law theorizing that
placed the sovereign status of Eastern powers in doubt and opened up the space
for a justification of norm-deviation. (Chatterjee, 2012: 188) The balance of
power system in Europe refocused attention away from conflict within Europe and
allowed states to pursue an aggressive form of colonization. (Chatterjee, 2012:
189) Industrial capitalism provided the impetus for colonial expansion as the
raw goods from the colonies were used in the production of capital goods, in a
reversal of previous flows of goods. This reversal provided the basis for the
global transformation that shifted material power heavily in favor the West.
(Chatterjee, 2012: 76) In the undercurrent of all these historical processes
was a racism of a myth of an Oriental despot and claims of superiority based on
race and religion, itself a product of historical modernity and Western
philosophies of progress. (Said 1978)
What one sees that is lacking in
Todorov is an acute awareness of the dialectic played out between the
historical modernity and the philosophical modernity. Norm-deviation is born of
specifically philosophies of progress but it is grounded also in the history of
colonial empire and born of a problem of colonial management. (Chatterjee,
2012: 174) Similarly norm-deviation provided a moral justification for the
extraction of capital that fed into the ‘great divergence’ between global North
and South. (Chatterjee, 2012: 191) These unequal power relations then could be
fed back into narratives of superiority and further justification for the
paternal despotism of colonial rule. With the bifurcation of Self and Other, imperial
interests can then be cloaked in the “moral rhetoric of war” (Chatterjee, 2012:
195) but with the consequence that, as Carl Schmitt observes (2007:54), “war
can be driven to the most extreme humanity.” What emerges from this interplay
is the “privilege to declare the exception to the norm.” (Chatterjee,
2012: 337) In this definition of an imperial practice through historical and
philosophical modernity we have a uniquely modern technique that produces a
colonial hierarchy.
Todorov in seeing a philosophical
solution that only needs to take place in the mind of the individual based on
equality and difference fails to see the deep structural and discursive causes
for colonial hierarchy that are marked by the interplay between history and
theory and emerge in a global practice of power. Like the eighteenth century
humanists who appealed to a universal humanity whose concept was “a polemical
denial of the then existing aristocratic-feudal system and the privileges
accompanying it,” (Schmitt, 2007: 55) Todorov denies the inherently political
nature of Self-Other relations as well as the deep, historical structural
causes underlying them. Todorov’s humanism and his romanticization of the
possibility to bring harmony to the world denote an explicit denial of the
social reality and the full implications of modernity. By staying true to
philosophical modernity’s ideals of progress and harmony through reason,
Todorov is limited in his critique. It is also important to note that in
Chatterjee’s account the voice and agency of the Other emerges in the
co-constitutive nature of the core and periphery that make modernity possible.
Returning to Todorov and his
philosophical solution to the problem of the Other reveals the inability of a
philosophical modernity rooted in the Enlightenment liberal tradition to come
to terms with the colonial consequences of historical modernity. Todorov’s
faith in the modern project that a path of non-violent communication can emerge
to destabilize solid identities and lead humanity to a more harmonious whole is
radically undermined when viewed from the point of view of the Other. Todorov’s
account speaks the language of equality and difference, but through his
silencing of the Other, invariably reproduces a claim of the superiority and
difference through the account of the ‘noble savage’ that he aims to
disprove. Furthermore, a reading of
Fanon’s The Wretched of the Earth
shows the limits to Todorov’s account of Self-Other relations and demonstrate
that the de Sahagun ideal of cross-cultural understanding cannot possibly be an
end in itself. Todorov speaks from the perspective of an outsider, claiming
witness to the situation of the Other and the best way to deal with the Other
while at the same time not allowing the Other to witness for himself. His
account shows that modernity is limited in its ability to understand itself by
the way it represents knowledge from an unacknowledged position of power. In
the gaze of Todorov, as in the gaze of de Sahagun, the possibility of speaking of
equality in difference is necessarily limited by the position of power from
which they speak.
For Fanon, Todorov’s solution of
equality in difference, if applied to a colonial context, would radically
underestimate that nature of violence endemic to the colonial situation. For
Fanon, Todorov’s move is one that aims to appeal to a native’s reason and
‘morality’ but in reality is a strategy to maintain a hierarchy. Fanon (2001:
33) demonstrates that “the colonized masses mock at these very values, insult them
and vomit them up.” He laughs because he is aware of the futility and
contradiction in Western values. The contradiction of Western values the native
sees in these values is their fundamental reliance on the principles of difference
and inferiority established by the norm-deviation structure and the figures of
Sepulveda and Las Casas. Fanon (2001: 33) recognizes that in order for Western logos to sustain itself it relies on a mythos of racial superiority. Fanon
points out “when the settler seeks to describe the native fully in exact terms
he refers to the bestiary.” Just as the norm-deviation structure relied on
mining different texts to demonstrate the inferiority of other civilizations
(Chatterjee, 2012: 179), Fanon’s settlers rely on the mythology of the native
as the embodiment of evil.Fanon also understands the “violence which has ruled
over the ordering of the colonial world” the settler uses in order to protect
their Western values and the binaries of ‘civilized’ Self and ‘barbaric’ Other.
The hypocrisy of Western values lies in their reliance on violence to maintain
the modern order, while in the same breath they preach peace.
The futility of Western values in
bringing about a successful end to a colonial hierarchy are limited by the fact
this reversal requires the very deconstructing of the system of colonization
that was created through violence. The only way to do this is through violence.
“The naked truth of decolonization evokes for us the searing bullets and
bloodstained knives which emanate from it.” (Fanon, 2001: 28) Todorov’s
inability to see this “naked truth” is due to the distance of his gaze, his
inability to live the experience of the Other and so his inability to truly
understand the nature of colonial hierarchies. Todorov and Bernadhino de
Sahagun’s empathetic gaze from afar would provide little consolation for Fanon.
While on the surface it appears like an exercise in solidarity, de Sahagun’s
reconstruction does little for the native’s actual existence. As Fanon (2001:
34) points out “no professor of ethics, no priest has ever come to be beaten in
his place, nor to share their bread with him.”
In Todorov’s account the Other is limited
to reacting instead of acting. Todorov invariably reproduces the myth of the
‘noble savage’ that he sets out to deconstruct by claiming that their using of
semiotics was inferior to that of the Europeans in understanding the Other. The
Aztecs are consistently displayed as naïve and Cortes, despite the violence he
incurs, a truly brilliant manipulator. (Todorov, 1999: 127) The only Aztec
character who assumes any agency in Todorov’s account (1999: 100-102) is La
Malinche, who from the perspective of Fanon and the oppressed, betrays her own
people and helps bring about their ruin. In Todorov’s romanticized account of
the non-West he points to the interaction between Self and Other as being
essential towards saving the West’s own humanity. Simultaneously he denies that
the Other should play any active role in this transformation and ignores the co-constitution
of the global order that made modernity possible.
Todorov’s (1999:248-249)
reproduction of the myth of the ‘noble savage’ and his argument that the spread
of Western values stems from a superiority in the understanding of the Other
indicates an ignorance of the co-constitution of the modern world but it also
indicates the limited gaze that attempts to represent the Other from a position
of power. In Todorov’s account the Other is never allowed to speak for himself.
Todorov (1999: 54) claims this is because of his sources, but in the same
moment dismisses it as trivial. Despite
Todorov’s claims to be proposing instead of imposing and that his account is
more myth than history, his reconstruction of a myth that claims to understand
our modern condition while leaving the native out would make Fanon’s words
(2001: 61)“For the native, objectivity is always directed against him” ring true.
Todorov’s moral testimony is one that requires the silence of the Other. From
the view of the Other, Todorov’s philosophy is just another artificial sentinel
turned to dust.
The Enlightenment, and even the beginnings of
modernity that precede it, are intrinsically tied to the idea of empire. By
ignoring the destructive power of capital and myth that is tied with logos
Todorov underestimates the social, political and economic consequences of
colonial modernity. Similarly in attempting to reconstruct a narrative that
seeks to explain the Other while silencing the Other, Todorov reveals the
limits of critiquing modernity from a philosophical position within modernity.
But even Fanon’s radical anti-colonial position remains committed to a ‘modern’
project. Fanon’s belief that violence can be controlled by rational means in
order to emancipate man into stage of humanity shows that we are all “heirs of
Marx.” (Derrida, 2006: 91) The tempting promise of emancipation offered by
modernity haunts both colonial and anti-colonial discourses. Instead I offer
the words of Walter Benjamin: “This storm irresistibly propels him into the
future to which his back is turned, while the pile of debris before him grows
skyward. This storm is what we call progress.” (Benjamin, 2007: 248) These
spectres of progress are not lost in the past but remain with us in our
contemporary society today.Intervention and destruction is justified in the
construction of the Other through Orientalism and Islamophobia, but it is tied
to capitalism, the nation-state and a number of other political, social and
economic institutions as well. If we truly wish to understand not only empire,
but international relations itself we have to understand the political, social
and economic institutions spawned by the co-constitution of colonial
hierarchical relations that are an essential part of modernity as well as the
nature of what it means to critique them.The above article is been take from academia which i found interesting and sharing to my readers.
No comments:
Post a Comment